Abstract

In 2000, Kadets et al. introduced the notions of acs, luacs, and uacs spaces, which form common generalisations of well-known rotundity and smoothness properties of Banach spaces. In a recent paper, the author introduced some further related notions and investigated the behaviour of these geometric properties under the formation of absolute sums. The present paper is in a sense a continuation of this work. Here we will study the behaviour of the said properties under the formation of Köthe-Bochner spaces, thereby generalising some results of G. Sirotkin on the acs, luacs, and uacs properties of -Bochner spaces.

1. Introduction

We begin with some notation and definitions. Throughout this paper, denotes a real Banach space, its dual, its unit ball and its unit sphere.

In the next definition, we summarise the most important rotundity properties.

Definition 1. A Banach space is called(i)rotund ( ) if for any two elements the equality implies , (ii)locally uniformly rotund (LUR) if for every , the implication holds for every sequence in , (iii)weakly locally uniformly rotund (WLUR) if for every and every sequence in one has (iv)uniformly rotund (UR) if for any two sequences and in the implication holds, (v)weakly uniformly rotund (WUR) if for any two sequences and the following implication holds:

Figure 1 shows the obvious implications between these notions. No other implications are valid in general (see the examples in [1]). Note, however, that all these notions coincide in finite-dimensional spaces, by the compactness of .

The modulus of convexity of the space is defined by for every in the interval . Then is UR if and only if for all .

For the local version one defines for every and each . Then is LUR if and only if for all and all .

Let us also recall some notions of smoothness. The space is called smooth ( ) if its norm is Gâteaux-differentiable at every nonzero point (equivalently at every point of ), which is the case if and only if for every there is a unique functional with (cf. [2, Lemma 8.4 (ii)]). is called Fréchet-smooth (FS) if the norm is Fréchet-differentiable at every nonzero point. The norm of the space is said to be uniformly Gâteaux-differentiable (UG) if for each the limit exists uniformly in . Finally, is called uniformly smooth (US) if , where denotes the modulus of smoothness of defined by for every .

In [3] the following notions were introduced (in connection with the so called Anti-Daugavet property).

Definition 2. A Banach space is called (i)alternatively convex or smooth (acs) if for every with and every with one has as well, (ii)locally uniformly alternatively convex or smooth (luacs) if for every , every sequence in and every functional one has (iii)uniformly alternatively convex or smooth (uacs) if for all sequences , in and in , one has The author introduced the following related notions in [4].

Definition 3. A Banach space is called(i)strongly locally uniformly alternatively convex or smooth (sluacs) if for every and all sequences in and in , one has (ii)weakly uniformly alternatively convex or smooth (wuacs) if for any two sequences , in and every functional , one has

The obvious implications between the acs properties and the rotundity properties are indicated in Figure 2. No other implications are generally valid (see the examples in [4]), but note again that the properties acs, luacs, sluacs, wuacs and uacs coincide in finite-dimensional spaces, by compactness.

The connection between some of the acs properties to smoothness properties is illustrated in Figure 3.

Let us mention that if we replace the condition by for every in the definitions of the properties uacs and sluacs, respectively we still obtain the same classes of spaces. For uacs spaces this was first proved by Sirotkin in [5] using the fact that uacs spaces are reflexive (see below). For sluacs spaces this characterisation can be proved by means of the Bishop-Phelps-Bollobás theorem (see [4, Proposition 2.1]).

This characterisation enables us to define the following “uacs-modulus” of a given Banach space (cf. [4, Definition 1.4]).

Definition 4. For a Banach space one defines Then is uacs if and only if for every and one clearly has for each .

The above characterisation shows that the class of uacs spaces coincides with the class of   -spaces introduced by Lau in [6] and our modulus is the same as the modulus of -convexity from [7]. Also, the notion of -spaces which was introduced in [8] coincides with the notion of acs spaces.

Recall that a Banach space is said to be uniformly nonsquare if there is some such that for all we have or . It is easily seen that uacs spaces are uniformly nonsquare and hence by a well-known theorem of James (cf. [9, page 261]) they are superreflexive, as was observed in [3, Lemma 4.4]. For a proof of the superreflexivity of uacs spaces that does not rely on James’ result on uniformly nonsquare spaces, see [4, Proposition 2.8].

Let us also restate here the following auxiliary result [4, Lemma 2.30] (it is the generalisation of [10, Lemma 2.1] to sequences, with a completely analogous proof).

Lemma 5. Let and be sequences in the (real or complex) normed space such that .
Then for any two bounded sequences , of nonnegative real numbers one also has .

Finally, we will need two more definitions from [4].

Definition 6. A Banach space is called (i)a space if for every , every sequence in with , and all one has (ii)a space if for every , every sequence in with , and all sequences in , one has Obviously, every WLUR space is , and every LUR space is .

In the next section we will recall some facts on Köthe-Bochner spaces.

2. Preliminaries on Köthe-Bochner Spaces

If not otherwise stated, will denote a complete, -finite measure space. For we denote by the characteristic function of .

A Köthe function space over is a Banach space of real-valued measurable (i.e., -Borel-measurable) functions on modulo equality -almost everywhere (we will henceforth abbreviate this by -a.e. or simply a.e. if is tacitly understood) such that (i) for every with , (ii)for every and every set with is -integrable over , (iii)if is measurable and such that -a.e., then and .

The standard examples are of course the spaces for .

Every Köthe function space is a Banach lattice when endowed with the natural order if and only if -a.e.

Recall that a Banach lattice is said to be order complete ( -order complete) if for every net (sequence) in which is order bounded, the supremum of said net (sequence) in exists. A Banach lattice is called order continuous ( -order continuous) provided that every decreasing net (sequence) in whose infimum is zero is norm-convergent to zero.

It is easy to see that a Köthe function space is always -order complete, and thus by [11, Proposition ] is order continuous if and only if is -order continuous if and only if is order complete and order continuous. Also, reflexivity of implies order continuity, for any -order complete Banach lattice which is not -order continuous contains an isomorphic copy of (cf. [11, Proposition  3.1.4]).

Let us also mention the following well-known fact that will be needed later.

Lemma 7. If is a Köthe function space, a sequence in , and such that , then there is a subsequence of which converges pointwise almost everywhere to .

For a Köthe function space we denote by the space of all measurable functions (modulo equality -a.e.) such that Then is again a Köthe function space, the so called Köthe dual of . The operator defined by is well-defined, linear and isometric. Moreover, is surjective if and only if is order continuous (cf. [11, page 149]), thus for order continuous we have .

We refer the reader to [12] or [11] for more information on Banach lattices in general and Köthe function spaces in particular.

Now recall that if is a Banach space, a function is called simple if there are finitely many disjoint measurable sets such that for all , is constant on each and for every . The function is said to be Bochner-measurable if there exists a sequence of simple functions such that -a.e. and weakly measurable if is measurable for every functional . According to Pettis’ measurability theorem (cf. [11, Theorem  3.2.2]) is Bochner-measurable if and only if is weakly measurable and almost everywhere separably valued (i.e., there is a separable subspace such that -a.e.).

For a Köthe function space and a Banach space we denote by the space of all Bochner-measurable functions (modulo equality a.e.) such that . Endowed with the norm becomes a Banach space, the so called Köthe Bochner space induced by and . The most prominent examples are again the Lebesgue-Bochner spaces for .

Next we recall how the dual of can be described provided that is order continuous. A function is called weak*-measurable if is measurable for every . We define an equivalence relation on the set of all weak*-measurable functions by setting if and only if for every a.e., and we write for the space of all (equivalence classes of) weak*-measurable functions such that there is some with a.e.

A norm on can be defined by Then the following deep theorem holds.

Theorem 8 (cf. [13]). Let be an order-continuous Köthe function space over the complete, -finite measure space , and let be a Banach space. Then the map defined by is an isometric isomorphism, and, moreover, every equivalence class in has a representative such that and .

There are a number of papers on various rotundity and smoothness properties in Köthe-Bochner spaces in general and Lebesgues-Bochner spaces in particular, see for example [1417] and references therein.

Sirotkin proved in [5] that for the Lebesgue-Bochner space is acs, respectively luacs, and uacs, whenever has the respective property. In the next section we will study the more general case of Köthe-Bochner spaces.

3. Results and Proofs

We begin with the acs spaces, for which we have the following result.

Proposition 9. If is an order-continuous acs Köthe function space and is an acs Banach space, then is acs as well.

Proof. The proof is similar to that of [4, Proposition 3.3]. First we fix two elements such that and a functional with .
Since is order continuous, by Theorem 8,   can be represented via an element such that and . It follows that and hence We also have and thus Since is acs it follows from (19) and (22) that In a similar way as we have obtained (22) we can also show Because is acs this together with (19), (22) and (23) implies From (19), (23) and (25) we get Now we will show that To this end, let us denote by and the null sets on which the equality from (20) and (26), respectively does not hold. Let .
Put and . We claim that is a null set.
To see this, define by for and for . Then is measurable and since for all we have with . We also have for every and hence by (19) which also implies . Together with (22) we now get since is acs. Taking into account (23) we arrive at Hence a.e. and thus must be a null set.
Now if then , and and as well as By [10, Lemma 2.1] this implies Since is acs it follows that .
So is a null set with for every and (27) is proved.
Now combining (23) and (27) we obtain which finishes the proof.

Before we turn to the case of luacs spaces, let us recall Egorov’s theorem (cf. [18, Theorem A, page 88]), which states that for any finite measure space and every sequence of measurable functions on which converges to zero pointwise -a.e. and each there is a set with such that is uniformly convergent to zero on .

Now we are ready to prove the following theorem.

Theorem 10. Let be an order-continuous Köthe function space over the complete -finite measure space and an luacs Banach space. If (a) is WLUR or (b) is and is also order continuous,then is also luacs.

Proof. Suppose that we are given a sequence in and an element such that as well as a functional such that . As before, we can represent by an element . We then have and hence By passing to a subsequence we may also assume that We further have and thus An analogous argument also shows Moreover, the inequality holds for every . It follows that Analogously one can see that Finally, we have Consequently Since is in particular luacs we get from (35) and (38) that Because is in any case , it follows from (41), (44), and (45) that and thus So by passing to a further subsequence we may assume Next we will show that Since is -finite there is an increasing sequence in such that for every and .
Denote by and the null sets on which the convergence statement from (36) and (48), respectively does not hold, and let . Put and . We will see that is a null set.
First we define for every a function by setting for and for . Note that each is measurable and since for every we have .
We have for every and every , so by Egorov’s theorem we can find for every an increasing sequence in with such that converges uniformly to zero on each .
It follows that is a null set for every .
Let us now first suppose that (b) holds, so is order continuous. We have and moreover this sequence is decreasing, so the order continuity of implies So if and are given, we can find an index such that , and then, by uniform convergence, an index such that for every and every .
Then we have for each .
In conclusion we have Now if (a) holds, that is, if is WLUR, then by (38) the sequence must be weakly convergent to in , and hence for all . Since decreases to zero a.e., the order continuity of gives us for every .
A similiar argument as before now easily yields that also holds in case (a). But is nothing else than Combining this with (35) leaves us with Since is luacs and because of (38), it follows that Taking into account (45) we get and hence for every we have a.e. Consequently, is a null set for every , and thus is also a null set.
Now suppose that . Then we have , and , as well as and By passing to a subsequence we may assume that is bounded away from zero. Then it follows from Lemma 5 that Also, we have Since is luacs we can conclude that .
So is a null set with for every and (49) is proved.
From (45) and (49) it follows that and we are done.

Recall that a subset is said to be equi-integrable if for every there is some such that It is well known that for a finite measure a bounded subset is relatively weakly compact in if and only if is equi-integrable (see, e.g., [19, Theorem 13.6]). One ingredient for the usual proof of this fact is the following lemma (see [19, Proposition 13.4]), which we will also need in the sequel.

Lemma 11. For a finite measure space , a sequence in is equi-integrable whenever the sequence is convergent for each .

We will also need Vitali’s lemma, which reads as follows (see, e.g., [11, Lemma  3.1.13] for an even more general version).

Lemma 12. Let be a finite measure space, and let be a sequence in such that is equi-integrable. Let be a measurable function on such that -a.e. Then and .

Finally, let us recall that a Banach space is said to have the Kadets-Klee property (also known as property ) if for every sequence in and each the implication holds. For example, every LUR space and every dual of a reflexive, FS space has the Kadets-Klee property.

It is known that every Banach lattice with the Kadets-Klee property is order continuous, (cf. [12, page 28]). With this in mind we can prove the following result concerning spaces.

Theorem 13. If the measure is finite and is LUR, then is a space whenever is . If in addition is order continuous then the assertion also holds if is merely -finite.

Proof. By the previous theorem, is luacs, so we only have to show the implication “ ” in Definition 6 (i). To this end, let be a sequence in and such that , and let such that . It will be enough to show that a subsequence of converges to one.
Since is order continuous, we can as before represent by some and conclude Also, just as we have done in the previous proof, we find that Since is LUR, it follows that Hence, by passing to a subsequence, we may assume that (cf. Lemma 7) By (67) and (64) we also have Since is , it follows from (65), (69) that From (67) we also get Thus by Lemma 11 the sequence and hence also the sequence are equi-integrable with respect to for every with . This combined with Vitali’s lemma and (71) implies So if , we immediately get because of (70).
If is merely -finite but is order continuous, we can fix an increasing sequence in such that and for every . Then the sequence decreases pointwise to zero, and, by the order continuity of , we can conclude that .
Thus given any , we find an such that . Since , there exists such that It follows that for every So we have and because of (70) it follows as before that finishing the proof.

Now we turn to the sluacs spaces. An easy normalisation argument shows that a Banach space is sluacs if and only if for every , every sequence in , and all sequences in with , and , we have . In view of this characterisation, is sluacs if and only if for every and every the number is strictly positive, where Next we will prove an easy lemma on the continuity of .

Lemma 14. For all , and all , one has that is is -Lipschitz continuous with respect to the norm of .

Proof. First we fix and . Put and take , such that . It follows that .
Now let be arbitrary. We can find with . Define . Then and hence But we have and as well as Thus we get and since was arbitrary, it follows that Again, since was arbitrary we can conclude that and by symmetry it follows that Analogously one can prove that for all and all , . An application of the triangle inequality then yields the result.

In the paper [16] Kamińska and Turett proved various theorems concerning different rotundity properties of Köthe-Bochner spaces. For example, by [16, Theorem 5] if has the so-called Fatou property and is LUR, then is LUR whenever is LUR. We will adopt the technique of proof from [16, Theorem 5] to show the following result.

Theorem 15. If is LUR and is sluacs smooth, then is also sluacs.

Proof. Since is LUR it is order continuous.
Let and be arbitrary and let for every . Since by the previous lemma is continuous, it follows that the sets are measurable. Also, the sequence is increasing and because is sluacs, we have ; hence decreases pointwise to zero. The order continuity of implies , and thus we can find with Now let us take and with and . Let be represented by . As in the proof of Proposition 9 we can conclude that Next we define Then is measurable, and Since , it follows that Let us fix such that Now consider the following sets: Then are measurable, pairwise disjoint, and . Thus by (96) there exists some such that If , then, since for , it follows that and again by definition of we obtain and hence In the case of one can obtain the same statement by an analogous argument. To treat the remaining cases we need some preliminary considerations.
Let us denote by the null set on which the equality from (93) does not hold and suppose that . Then in particular and , and hence Moreover, by the definitions of and and the choice of we have Since , we also have So by definition of we must have Once more by the definition of this implies where .
Now suppose that . Then Consequently Since , the definition of implies that where the latter inequality holds because of . It follows that where which by (97) is greater than zero. Because of , it follows that So if we put and , then Now we will show that if and , respectively then Let us first assume that , that is, Since for it follows that Because is a null set, we have where the second last inequality holds because of (91).
Now assume that ; that is, It follows that and hence as before we get So if , or then there is such that Put . Then , and moreover ; hence We further have Altogether we have shown that, for we have for every and every with and By the aforementioned characterisation of sluacs spaces ([4, Proposition 2.1]), this implies that is sluacs.

Next we will have a look at the case of wuacs spaces.

Theorem 16. If is a -finite measure and is wuacs, reflexive, and has the Kadets-Klee property, then is wuacs whenever is wuacs.

Proof. Note that since is reflexive (or since it has the Kadets-Klee property), it is order continuous.
Let us take two sequences and in the unit sphere of such that and a functional , as usual represented by , with .
As in the proof of Theorem 10 we find and by passing to a subsequence also It is also easy to see that Since is wuacs, it follows from (126) and (128) that Again since is wuacs and because of (126), (128), (129), and (130) we can deduce that Hence we can pass to a further subsequence such that By the reflexivity of we can pass once more to a subsequence such that and are weakly convergent to and , respectively. In view of (126) and (130) it follows that hence , and moreover The fact that has the Kadets-Klee property implies that and thus by Lemma 7 we can, for the last time, pass to a subsequence such that Let , , and denote the null sets on which the convergence statement from (127), (132), and (136), respectively, does not hold and put as well as and .
Because of (134) and since is in particular acs, we can show just as in the proof of Proposition 9 that is a null set.
The fact that is wuacs together with Lemma 5 easily implies that By the weak convergence of to we have Since is reflexive, is order continuous, and thus we can deduce as in the proof of Theorem 13, with the aid of Vitali’s lemma, (138), (137), and the fact that is a null set, that Because of (130), it follows that and we are done.

If we combine the techniques of the proofs of Theorems 16 and 13, we can also obtain another result concerning spaces (we omit the details).

Theorem 17. If is a -finite measure and is , reflexive and has the Kadets-Klee property, then is whenever is .

It is further possible to obtain another sufficient condition for to be sluacs.

Theorem 18. If is a -finite measure and is and reflexive and both and have the Kadets-Klee property, then is sluacs whenever is sluacs.

Proof. Let be a sequence in and such that we have . Also, let be a sequence in such that . If we represent each by , we can obtain as usual and by passing to a subsequence also as well as Using the fact that is we can conclude that So we can pass to another subsequence such that Since (and hence also ) is reflexive, we may assume without loss of generality that is weakly convergent to some and that is weakly convergent to some .
It follows from (148) that and hence . Because of (151), (143), and the fact that is , we get that and consequently whence . Since both and have the Kadets-Klee property, it follows that Thus we can pass once more to a subsequence such that Combining (153) and (151) we also obtain Let be a null set such that the convergence statements of (142), (150), and (155) hold for every , and put as well as .
Similar to the arguments in the proof of Theorem 16 one can see that is a null set and then, using the fact that is sluacs, deduce that By our usual method based on Vitali’s lemma we can conclude that for every with we have Now we fix an increasing sequence in such that for all and . The order continuity of implies . Analogous to the argument at the end of the proof of Theorem 13, this together with (158) leads to Taking into account (148) we arrive at and the proof is finished.

Next we will consider sufficient conditions for a Köthe-Bochner space to be (recall that a dual Banach space is said to have the Kadets-Klee* property if it fulfils the definition of the Kadets-Klee property with weak-replaced by weak*-convergence).

Theorem 19. Let be a Köthe function space over the complete -finite measure space , and let be an Banach space. If has the Kadets-Klee* property and in addition (a) is , reflexive, and has the Kadets-Klee property or (b) is LUR and is weak*-sequentially compact,then is .

Proof. By Theorems 15 and 18 we already know that is in both cases sluacs. Note also that in both cases is order continuous. Now take a sequence in and such that , and let be a sequence in such that . If we represent each by we can obtain as usual and by passing to a subsequence also as well as Since is , it follows that so that by passing to another subsequence we can assume In both cases (a) and (b) the dual unit ball is weak*-sequentially compact, so that we can also assume the weak*-convergence of to some . It follows from (161) that and hence . Since has the Kadets-Klee* property, we get and thus we can, by passing to yet another subsequence, assume that Next we claim that there is an such that and, after passing to a subsequence once more, In case (b) is LUR, and thus by (163) and (171) we can take . In case (a) is reflexive, and hence we can assume that is weakly convergent to some . Then (174) follows from (172) and (168). This also implies , and by the Kadets-Klee property of we have (175).
By (175) we may assume that Note that (171) and (174) imply that . Using all this and the fact that is one can first prove, analogously to the arguments in the proof of Theorem 18, that and then for every with .
Let us now fix a sequence in as in the proof of Theorem 18. The order continuity of implies .
Let be arbitrary. Since is there exists a such that for all and all with and one has .
Fix with . Because of (163), (161) and (178) there is an such that for all the inequalities hold.
It follows that for every we have and hence by the choice of , Consequently, for every we have Thus we have shown Together with (168) it follows , as desired.

Now let us treat the case of uacs spaces. In analogy to [4, Definition 3.15] we say that an order continuous Köthe function space has property if for every there is some such that for all and every we have This property certainly implies that is uacs, while every UR space has property , but the author does not know whether these implications are strict.

The following theorem holds. Its proof is completely analogous to the one of [4, Theorem 3.16] (which is a modification of the proof of [20, Theorem 3]), but we will explicitly give it here, for the readers convenience.

Theorem 20. If is an order continuous Köthe function space with the property (in particular, if is UR) and is a uacs Banach space, then is also uacs.

Proof. Let be arbitrary. Since is in particular uacs there is a number such that for all functions and every functional with one has Now let such that a.e., and let such that and . We claim that .
Let be represented by , and put , . Define by . Note that is measurable and As before we can deduce from that and a.e., hence Next we define Note that since is continuous on (see [21, Lemma 3.10] or [4, Lemma 2.11]), the function is measurable. Using (188) it is easy to see that By (186) and (187) we have . Furthermore, we also have thus Now put and . We then have (because of (187)) Together with (192) it follows that Taking into account (186) we get Next we define and as well as . Then . Let be the functional on represented by . We have (by (187)) and further, by (195), So by our choice of we get ; that is, By monotonicity of we have Using (190), (198), and (197) we obtain The first step of the proof is completed. Next we wish to remove the restriction a.e. So let again be arbitrary, and choose as above but corresponding to the value . Take .
Since is uacs, we may find such that for all and every we have Next we fix and find a number to the value according to the definition of the property of . Finally, let .
Let be arbitrary and (as usually represented by ) such that and . We are going to prove that , thus showing that is uacs.
To this end, we define by Then is Bochner-measurable, and for all (hence ). Furthermore, As before we have Also, so the choice of together with (202) implies Next we observe that and (because of (203) and (205)) So (200) implies Using (205) and (208) we can conclude By the choice of this implies . But by (205) we also have ; hence .

The above theorem admits the following corollary.

Corollary 21. If is a US Köthe function space and is a uacs Banach space, and hence also is uacs.

Proof. Since uacs is a self-dual property (cf. [4, Corollary 2.13]) is also uacs, and since is US, we have that is UR (cf. [2, Theorem 9.10]). So by the previous theorem is uacs. But as a uacs space, is reflexive, and hence it has the Radon-Nikodým property. It follows from the general theory in [13] that in this case is isometrically isomorphic to , so and hence also is uacs.

Finally, we consider some midpoint version of luacs and sluacs spaces. Let us first recall the following well-known notions: a Banach space is said to be midpoint locally uniformly rotund (MLUR) if for any two sequences and in and every we have is called weakly midpoint locally uniformly rotund (WMLUR) if it satisfies the above condition with replaced by , where the symbol denotes the convergence in the weak topology of . The notion of MLUR spaces was originally introduced by Anderson in [22].

In [4] the author introduced the following analogous definitions.

Definition 22. Let be a Banach space.(i)The space is said to be midpoint locally uniformly alternatively convex or smooth (mluacs) if for any two sequences and in , every , and every , one has (ii)The space is called midpoint strongly locally uniformly alternatively convex or smooth (msluacs) if for any two sequences and in , every and every sequence in , one has
Figure 4 summarises the obvious implications. No other implications are true in general (see the examples in [4]).

Concerning the properties msluacs and mluacs for Köthe-Bochner spaces we have the following result.

Theorem 23. Let be an MLUR Köthe function space over a complete -finite measure space and a Banach space. If is mluacs, then so is . If is msluacs and in addition has the Kadets-Klee* property and is weak*-sequentially compact, then is also msluacs.

Proof. Let us first recall that has no equivalent MLUR norm (cf. [11, Theorem ]), and so by [11, Propositions and ] (and since every Köthe function space is -order complete), must be order continuous.
Now let us assume that is msluacs and has the Kadets-Klee* property and weak*-sequentially compact unit ball. To show that is msluacs we will proceed in an analogous way to the proof of [4, Proposition 4.7], which in turn uses techniques from the proof of [23, Proposition 4].
So let us take two sequences , in and such that . Also, take a sequence of norm-one functionals on such that . As usual, will be represented by , and we conclude and, after passing to an appropriate subsequence, We also have hence As before we can also show Also, because of , we may pass to a further subsequence such that Let us define for every Note that So if , then If , then So we always have It follows that and we can conclude with (216) and (217) that .
Using this together with (216), , and the fact that is MLUR we get Again, since is MLUR, this implies Because of (225) and (226), we can pass to a further subsequence such that Since is weak*-sequentially compact we may also asssume that weak*-converges to some .
Equations (225) and (226) imply . Together with (213) this gives us hence we also have thus . Since has the Kadets-Klee* property, it follows that , so if we pass again to a subsequence, we may assume Now if we combine (214), (216), (227), and (230) we obtain since is msluacs.
Using our usual argument via equi-integrability and Vitali’s lemma this leads to for every with .
By the order continuity of we can derive from this also in the -finite case (cf. the proof of Theorem 18).
Combining (233) and (228) gives us , and we are done.
The statement about mluacs spaces can be proved similarly.

We remark that the results proved in this section especially apply to spaces for (as we said before, for the properties acs/luacs/uacs this was already proved by Sirotkin in [5]).

Corollary 24. If is acs/luacs/ /sluacs/ /mluacs/msluacs/wuacs/uacs, then for any complete, -finite measure space and any the Lebesgue-Bochner space has the same property.

In the last section we will establish some further connections between the various properties that we considered in this paper.

4. Miscellaneous

In [24] Lovaglia called a Banach space weakly locally uniformly rotund if for every sequence in , every and each , the implication holds. Since this notion of weak local uniform rotundity is strictly weaker than the notion of WLUR spaces that is nowadays commonly used, we will call such spaces WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia. (A dual Banach space will be called WLUR* in the sense of Lovaglia, if it fulfils Lovaglia’s definition for all evaluation functionals.) By definition, a Banach space is if and only if it is luacs and WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia. Also, the following is valid.

Proposition 25. A Banach space is if and only if is WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia and for all with and every with one also has .

Proof. The necessity is clear because of [4, Proposition 2.16 (i)]. For the sufficiency we only have to prove that is luacs, so let us take a sequence in and such that as well as with . Since is weak*-compact, we can find and a subnet which is weak*-convergent to . It follows that .
Now fix a sequence in such that . Then and . There are and a subnet which is weak*-convergent to . It follows that . Since is WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia, we conclude . It follows that ; hence .
Because of , our assumption implies and we are done.

The following assertion is also easy to prove (we omit the details).

Proposition 26. If is a Banach space which is WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia, and such that is WLUR* in the sense of Lovaglia then is sluacs.

Under additional assumptions on the space it is possible to prove some more results.

Proposition 27. Let be a reflexive Banach space. (i)If is WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia, then is .(ii)If is sluacs and , then is wuacs.(iii)If is wuacs and , then is WLUR.

Proof. (i) follows directly from the Proposition 25 and [4, Proposition 2.15]. Of the remaining assertions we will only prove (iii) explicitly.
Let be a sequence in and such that . We can find a sequence in such that , and hence and .
Since is reflexive, we may assume that is weak*-convergent to some and is weakly convergent to some . It follows that and hence .
Since is wuacs, the dual space is sluacs (cf. [4, Proposition 2.16]), and thus (because of ) we can conclude that , whence , which implies , which by the rotundity of implies .

Proposition 28. Let be a reflexive Banach space with the Kadets-Klee property. (i)If is acs then , is luacs.(ii)If is WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia, then is wuacs and .(iii)If is WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia and , then is wuacs and LUR.

Proof. (i) Let , , and be as in the proof of (iii) of the previous proposition and let with . Then and hence . Since has the Kadets-Klee property, it follows that and thus . Because is acs, we obtain , as desired.
(ii) We first show that is wuacs. Take two sequences and in such that and a functional with . By the reflexivity of we may assume that is weakly convergent to some . Then ; hence .
But has the Kadets-Klee property, so this implies .
Now fix a sequence in such that , and . It follows that and consequently .
Since and is WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia, we get , proving that is wuacs.
Now we will show that is sluacs. Take and in with and a sequence in such that . Also, fix a sequence in with and .
We may assume that is weakly convergent to some and is weak*-convergent to some . It follows that , and hence .
Since is wuacs, is sluacs, and thus we get . It follows that ; hence and . The Kadets-Klee property of gives us .
Because of , we can now infer . Since is in particular acs, this implies (cf. [4, Proposition 2.19]).
We will skip the last part of the proof, the reverse implication in the definition of .
(iii) By (ii) is wuacs and . Let us take a sequence in and an element such that . Fix a sequence in such that , for every . Since is sluacs, it follows that .
Assume that is weakly convergent to and that is weak*-convergent to . It follows that and hence . Moreover, since is WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia, we get that .
Since converges weakly to this implies and hence . Now the Kadets-Klee property of allows us to conclude .
Because of , we must have and thus the rotundity of implies .

Proposition 29. Let be a Banach space such that has the Kadets-Klee* property and is weak*-sequentially compact. (i)If is , then it is also WLUR in the sense of Lovaglia.(ii)If is acs, then is , and for all sequences   in , in and every with and one has . (iii) If is WLUR* in the sense of Lovaglia, then is sluacs.

Proof. We will only prove (iii), so let and be in with and a sequence in such that . Let be a sequence in with and .
By assumption, we may suppose that is weak*-convergent to some . Then ; hence . By the Kadets-Klee* property of we must have .
It follows that ; hence . Since is WLUR* in the sense of Lovaglia, we obtain .